Posts

Writing as Origin: Derrida, Nietzsche, Saussure and the Systemic Genesis of Meaning

Bild
Introduction In Of Grammatology , Derrida radically reinterprets the function of writing, not as a derivative of speech but as the foundational structure of meaning itself. Nowhere is this more clearly articulated than in the section The Written Being / The Being Written , where he draws heavily on Nietzsche to advance his deconstruction of logocentrism. Nietzsche's contribution is pivotal: he treats writing not as a secondary inscription of thought or truth, but as a constitutive act that generates meaning. Derrida encapsulates this when he observes: “Nietzsche has written what he has written. He has written that writing—and first of all his own—is not originarily subordinate to the logos and to truth.” (1) This position has profound linguistic and philosophical consequences. It implies that meaning does not derive from an external origin or metaphysical ground but is born within the very system of signs. Derrida’s formulation—“il n’y a pas de hors-texte,” or “there is no...

When Thought Escapes the Thinker: Wittgenstein, Nietzsche, and the Autonomy of Language

Bild
  Introduction Philosophical writing often appears as the product of deliberate, structured reasoning—a thinker consciously shaping arguments to construct a coherent system. Yet, there are moments when a philosopher’s own work seems to outgrow its creator, developing beyond their control and forcing them to abandon their original intentions. Two striking cases of this phenomenon can be found in Ludwig Wittgenstein and Friedrich Nietzsche. Wittgenstein, in the preface to Philosophical Investigations , acknowledges that he initially attempted to present his later work alongside Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus , only to realize that the gap between the two was insurmountable. Likewise, Nietzsche began Beyond Good and Evil as a continuation of The Dawn , but as he transcribed the manuscript, he became convinced that it had taken on a radically different tone and depth. In both cases, the authors were led by the momentum of their own evolving thought, eventually forced to recognize ...

The Limits of Principle II: Nietzsche and the Stoic Exception in Marcus Aurelius

Bild
Introduction This article serves as a follow-up to The Limits of Principle: Nietzsche and the Stoic Exception , where we examined Nietzsche’s complex relationship with Epictetus. In that discussion, we saw how Nietzsche both admired and criticized Stoicism, appreciating Epictetus' emphasis on self-mastery while rejecting Stoicism as a rigid system that attempts to impose order on an inherently chaotic world. Now, we turn to Marcus Aurelius, another Stoic figure whose thought provides a different challenge for Nietzsche. Unlike Epictetus, who came from a background of literal slavery, Marcus was an emperor—a "master" in Nietzschean terms. How would Nietzsche have interpreted Marcus’ reflections on humility, mortality, and the stripping away of illusions? This article explores Marcus Aurelius’ famous passage from Meditations , Book 6.13, where he deconstructs the grandeur of life into its base material components, and the anecdote of his assistant reminding him, “Y...

The Limits of Principle: Nietzsche and the Stoic Exception

Bild
The Soldier’s Dilemma One day, a soldier on the front received urgent news: his father was dying and wished to see him one last time. Without hesitation, he rushed back to town. Upon arriving at the bedside, the frail old man reached out and whispered, “Is that you, my son?” In that moment, the soldier realized the terrible mistake—this was not his father. A choice lay before him: should he correct the error, denying the dying man his final comfort, or should he let him pass in peace, knowing the truth would only bring distress? Lying is wrong in principle, but does this case demand an exception? This dilemma captures the tension between rigid principles and contextual flexibility—a tension that also runs through Nietzsche’s engagement with Stoicism. While he critiques Stoicism as a dogmatic system, he recognizes its value when applied as a personal ethic of strength. His position, much like the soldier’s, is not one of outright rejection or blind adherence, but of context-depe...